Introduction
Deliberation’s effectiveness as a method of conflict resolution and democratic decision making is often seen as stemming from the persuasive power of the forceless force of argument. But can an approach to deliberation based on persuasion successfully resolve contemporary conflicts related to partisan polarization, conspiracy theories, or COVID-19, which may be deeply connected to citizens’ social identities? Results from social psychology suggest that, in conflicts such as these, approaches to deliberation based on persuasion and reason-giving may be unproductive, due to the motivated reasoning we unconsciously deploy in response to arguments that threaten our social identity. In these situations, a deliberative process based around co-creation rather than persuasion may be more likely to produce positive deliberative transformations, while still adhering to core deliberative norms.
In this paper I first discuss the importance of social identity to many of the contemporary conflicts that deliberation must help to resolve if it is to serve as an effective basis of democratic legitimacy. I also argue that modern conceptions of deliberation tend to see persuasion by the force of argument as the primary mechanism by which deliberation can induce belief change among participants. I then show that when the conclusions of an argument threaten participants’ social identity they are likely to engage in motivated reasoning, which inhibits the ability of any argument to induce belief change. I argue that Mary Parker Follett’s (1918, 1924) conception of integration, which can be seen as an alternative approach to deliberation based on co-creation, may be more productive than persuasion-based approaches in conflicts closely related to social identity. I illustrate this by contrasting deliberative approaches based on persuasion and co-creation to the contemporary conflict between vaccine advocates and members of the vaccine hesitancy and refusal (VHR) community.
Social Identity and Deliberative Democracy
Social identity theory argues that identifications with social groups are important components of our self-esteem (Tajfel & Turner, 1979). We can identify with different groups simultaneously, but we may identify more strongly with some than others, and the salience of a particular identity can wax and wane depending on the context. The increasing relevance of social identity to deliberative democracy is evidenced by the central role that social identity appears to play in many of the most contentious contemporary political conflicts. Partisanship, which has long been seen as a key barrier to deliberation (Dryzek, 2017, p. 613; Owen & Smith, 2015, p. 229) is itself a powerful form of social identity (Green, Palmquist, & Schickler, 2002; West & Iyengar, 2020), and research argues that the increasing contentiousness of the US political environment is not due to increasing polarization with respect to particular issue positions, but rather the increasing emotional salience and affective polarization of partisan social identity (Abramowitz & McCoy, 2019; Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra, & Westwood, 2019; Mason, 2018). The waxing importance of social identity in the political sphere has also been implicated in the rise of ‘post truth politics’ and political conspiracy theories, as well as declining trust in scientific evidence in favor of identity-supporting beliefs (Dryzek et al., 2019; Sternisko, Cichocka, & Bave, 2020). The epistemological implications of social identity may also strongly impact behaviors and attitudes related to public health crises, like the COVID-19 pandemic. Past research has found that skepticism of vaccines and mainstream medical science are often driven not by ignorance, but rather by totalizing belief systems that form a central part of skeptics’ social identity (Attwell & Smith, 2017; Ward, Attwell, Meyer, Rokkas, & Leask, 2017). Similar dynamics are likely to underlie some of the public skepticism surrounding efforts to minimize the spread of COVID-19 or the safety and efficacy of newly developed vaccines (Cruwys, Stevens, & Greenawa, 2020).
Regardless of how or where deliberative democracy is instantiated—be it within legislative bodies (Goodin, 2008), in minipublics or deliberative town halls (Neblo, Esterling, & Lazer, 2018), through ‘participatory constitutionalism’ (Lafont, 2020), or in the public sphere of media discourse (Habermas, 2006)—its utility as a basis for democratic legitimacy in contemporary society depends on its ability to successfully resolve conflicts like these that are closely related to social identity. If, by contrast, deliberation were only effective in conflicts where the topics being debated had little or no implications for the social identities of participants, then it would be ill-suited for solving the ‘crisis of democracy’ that many societies have found themselves facing (Dryzek et al., 2019). It is therefore critical to understand the ways in which social identity impacts the success or failure of the deliberative process. Recent work has already started to investigate these questions, arguing that increasing the salience of social identity in deliberation could prevent groupthink or polarization (Batalha, Niemeyer, Dryzek, & Gastil, 2019) and that opposing social identities can inhibit the acceptance of deliberative norms (Strickler, 2018). However, deliberative theory has yet to consider how the psychological consequences of social identity threat may inhibit what many deliberative theorists see as the central mechanism for deliberation-induced belief change: persuasion through the forceless force of argument.
Deliberation and Persuasion through the Forceless Force
Although deliberation can serve many functions in society, and can produce many beneficial outcomes, its importance for democratic theory stands or falls on its effectiveness as a method of conflict resolution and decision making (Bächtiger, Dryzek, Mansbridge, & Warren, 2018; Goodin, 2017). To fulfill these functions, a deliberation must necessarily lead to some form of belief change among at least some of the participants. Although deliberative theory has moved away from consensus as an explicit goal of deliberation, there is still wide agreement that deliberation ‘would have no point if it did not produce change in the views of at least some participants’ (Mansbridge et al., 2010, p. 78). Alternately, as Goodin (2000, p. 88) puts it, ‘people change their minds over the course of the deliberation (it would hardly be a genuine deliberation at all if they did not, at least sometimes).’ Of course, the transformations produced by deliberation may not involve the particular positions being debated. Rather, participants may be convinced, in the course of deliberation, to revise their ‘meta-beliefs’ about the legitimacy of the values being articulated, the epistemic standards that should be applied, or the range of acceptable alternatives (Dryzek & Niemeyer, 2006). Nevertheless, even in these situations, deliberative success still requires that participants exit the deliberation with different meta-beliefs than they entered with. It is for this reason that deliberation’s ability to actually produce belief change under different circumstances is such a pressing question within deliberative theory (Fishkin & Luskin, 2005; Mackie, 2006; Zhang, 2019) and that documented examples of deliberative transformation are cited as rebuttals to claims that deliberation is unrealistic or ineffective (Dryzek et al., 2019).1
However, because deliberation is, by definition, non-coercive, it must possess one or more mechanisms for inducing participants to change their beliefs in the absence of coercive force, including the physical inducements deployed in bargaining. Although there are a number of possible mechanisms by which deliberation could induce belief change, current understandings of deliberation have tended to focus almost exclusively on what Neblo et al. (2018, p. 86) refer to as the ‘leading idea’ of deliberative democracy: persuasion via the ‘forceless force (zwanglose Zwang) of the better argument’ (Habermas, 1996, p. 306).2
Persuasion, in this context, refers to a process by which an argument produces a forceless (i.e., non-coercive) force of sufficient strength to induce participants in a deliberation to change their minds. The centrality of persuasion to modern understandings of deliberation can be seen in efforts to clarify how deliberation differs from other forms of communication, such as when Mansbridge et al. (2012, p. 18) distinguish deliberation from coercion by noting that ‘deliberation is about genuine persuasion, not pressure.’ Dryzek (2005, p. 224) likewise sees deliberation as distinguished from agonism because deliberation is ‘oriented to persuasion.’3 Even when the term itself is not explicitly invoked, some form of persuasion is implicitly endorsed as the primary deliberative mechanism for belief change whenever deliberation is defined as primarily about the giving and evaluation of ‘reasons’ for or against particular positions (e.g. Dryzek, 2017, p. 612; Goodin, 2000, p. 81; Owen & Smith, 2015, p. 228).4 Critically, these definitions often tacitly assume that deliberation is mainly (or exclusively) concerned with debating and justifying pre-existing ideas that participants had already formulated prior to the deliberation, as opposed to the creation of genuinely new ideas within the deliberation itself.5 In formal mathematical models of deliberation, this assumption—that deliberation involves adjudicating between a set of pre-formulated alternatives—is often stated explicitly (e.g. Chung & Duggan, 2020; List, 2018). In this conception, then, deliberation can only produce belief change insofar as participants are persuaded by a sufficiently strong argument to reject positions or beliefs (including, of course, meta-beliefs about epistemology or values) that they previously held or to adopt the pre-existing positions or beliefs of their opponents.
The strength of an argument or reason is not, of course, decided by reference to some a priori standard for rationality, but by criteria established within the deliberation by participants themselves.6 Deliberative theory has also begun to move away from a focus on rational justification and now tends to see storytelling, humor, ‘testifying,’ and many other forms of communication as permitted ‘reasons’ in a deliberation (Bächtiger, Niemeyer, Neblo, Steenbergen, & Steiner, 2010; Dryzek, 2000). Successful deliberative persuasion merely requires that, by whatever standard of evaluation a participant is employing—logical coherence, emotional appeal, humor, or something else—an argument (which could include a compelling story, joke, or testimonial) is judged to be sufficiently strong to compel belief change.
For conceptions of deliberation based on persuasion and reason-giving, successfully resolving conflicts is therefore dependent on the power of persuasion to induce belief change via the forceless force of argument. Deliberation is thus less likely to successfully resolve conflicts when—regardless of what types of reasons are permitted or provided, or how these reasons are evaluated—the processes of argumentation and persuasion in general lose their ability to induce belief change. Unfortunately, empirical research in social psychology suggests that is precisely what can occur in response to social identity threat.
Social Identity Threat and Motivated Reasoning
Given that our sense of self-identity is constructed in reference to the groups we identify with (Tajfel & Turner, 1979) it makes sense that information or arguments that threaten the perceived value of these groups could represent an existential threat to our own self-identity (Breakwell, 2015). Research has found that in response to social identity threat we unconsciously engage in various defensive mechanisms to minimize the damage to our self-esteem, especially if we strongly identify with the group in question (Branscombe, Ellemers, Spears, & Dooje, 1999). These defense mechanisms can include not only heightened in-group affect and out-group hostility but also various forms of biased information processing (Cohen, Aronson, & Steele, 2000; Nauroth, Gollwitzer, Bender, & Rothmund, 2014; Nauroth, Gollwitzer, Kozuchowski, Bender, & Rothmund, 2017). Most salient for deliberative democracy, however, are repeated empirical findings that threats to social identity lead individuals to engage in motivated reasoning (Cohen et al., 2007; Dalton & Huang, 2013; Hoog, 2012; Slothuus & Vreese, 2010).7
When engaged in motivated reasoning, we evaluate arguments not with an orientation towards accuracy but with a goal of maintaining our existing values, identities, and political preferences (Kahan, 2015; Kunda, 1990; Taber & Lodge, 2006). This poses a challenge for efforts to induce belief change through persuasion when the beliefs we are motivated to maintain are themselves the subject of argument. Motivated reasoning undermines the ability of better arguments to induce belief change by reducing the perceived quality of arguments that would compel us to change our minds with respect to the belief in question. This effect is clearly not limited to any particular type of argument or standard of evaluation. When subject to motivated reasoning, I will evaluate any argument against my preferred position as weaker precisely because accepting it would force me to change my mind.
Even more troubling, perhaps, is the power of cognitive biases like motivated reasoning to prevent participants from engaging in productive deliberation even if they wish to do so. Discussions about the deliberative capacity of individual citizens often concern the question of whether they are willing to change their minds in the face of persuasion,8 implying, perhaps unintentionally, that the success of deliberation depends on whether citizens choose to have an open mind and consider opposing arguments fairly. But research has repeatedly demonstrated that motivated reasoning and other forms of biased information processing operate unconsciously (Kahan, 2015; Taber & Lodge, 2016) and are usually invisible to those they affect. Even when we are made aware of the pervasiveness of motivated reasoning, and can identify it in others, experimental studies have shown that humans possess a ‘bias blind spot’ that prevents us from noticing when we are engaging in it ourselves (Kukucka, Kassin, Zapf, & Drorc, 2017; Pronin, Gilovich, & Ross, 2004; Pronin, Lin, & Ross, 2002). I may honestly and deeply believe that I am interpreting opposing arguments charitably, and that I would be willing to revise my beliefs in the face of a sufficiently compelling argument, but the unconscious operation of motivated reasoning may prevent this from ever actually occurring in practice.
Partly for these reasons, past work has already warned that motivated reasoning represents a serious threat to deliberative democracy (Richey, 2012; Rosenberg, 2014). However, although it is clear that motivated reasoning can present deliberation from changing minds, it is equally clear that it does not always do so. It is not infinitely powerful; opposing evidence can sometimes compel belief change even in the face of motivated reasoning (Már & Gastil, 2020; Redlawsk, Civettini, & Emmerson, 2010). Furthermore, research confirms that group deliberation can produce belief change even in regard to contentious topics in politically polarized societies (Barabas, 2004; Neblo et al., 2018), although it is also true that certain beliefs are more resistant to change than others (Zhang, 2019).
However, the fact that motivated reasoning serves as a psychological defense mechanism for social identity threat implies that it is especially likely to inhibit deliberation’s ability to productively resolve many of the pressing contemporary conflicts related to partisan polarization, conspiracy theories, and the reliability of mainstream science, all of which are closely connected to social identity. Even if participants in a debate over one of these topics avoid challenging each other’s social identities directly, they may still experience social identity threat in response to arguments over other beliefs that they view as having implications for the value of a social group they strongly identify with. Because revising these beliefs would threaten their social identity, we can expect participants to unconsciously deploy motivated reasoning to avoid having to change their minds, even in the face of what they might otherwise consider convincing evidence. For example, if I strongly identify as a libertarian, then my self-esteem is partly dependent on the (perceived) truth of certain beliefs that I view as an inherent part of what it means to be a libertarian (e.g., that reducing government intervention in the economy will tend to increase social welfare). A good argument that this belief is actually false would therefore represent a serious threat to my social identity and self-esteem. Through motivated reasoning I can construct a justification for rejecting this argument, thereby preserving my self-esteem, but in doing so, I forestall any possibility of it changing my mind.
Social identity threat may similarly prevent deliberative persuasion from achieving ‘meta-consensus’ (Dryzek & Niemeyer, 2006). For example, in an epistemic meta-consensus, participants may still disagree about the truth of various claims but are operating from within a similar epistemic paradigm (Kuhn, 1970), which allows for common standards of evidence and reasonableness. Achieving an epistemic meta-consensus requires that, for example, participants agree that claims backed only by ‘partisan’ sources should not be admitted into the debate (Dryzek & Niemeyer, 2006, p. 646). However, perceptions of whether a source is partisan or credible are themselves influenced by social identity. When scientific evidence affirms social identity it is more likely to believed, but when evidence from the same source threatens social identity, not only are individuals less likely to believe it, but they also lower their opinion of the credibility of the scientists who produced it (Nauroth et al., 2014; Nauroth et al., 2017). Similarly, epistemic paradigms themselves (e.g., a distrust of mainstream media (Schulz, Wirth, & Müller, 2020) or skepticism of ‘western science’ (Ward et al., 2017)) can serve as key components of social identity. Attempts to persuade individuals to reject these epistemic frameworks in order to achieve epistemic meta-consensus may therefore still provoke social identity threat and motivated reasoning.
We have therefore identified an important weakness in conceptions of deliberation that treat reason giving and persuasion by the force of argument as the sole or primary mechanism for inducing belief change. In a deliberation where salient beliefs and opinions are strongly connected to participants’ social identities, motivated reasoning may prevent any argument from being perceived as strong enough to induce belief change. Given that conflicts related to social identity are among the most pressing and contentious in contemporary society, it is worth considering whether, in these situations, there is some other mechanism by which deliberation could induce belief change.
One possibility involves relaxing the often tacit assumption that deliberation is primarily concerned with adjudicating between pre-existing beliefs, because it is the pre-existing connection of these beliefs to participants’ social identity that is the source of the difficulty. If deliberation instead led participants to jointly develop new beliefs, then this would represent a way in which participants’ minds could be changed without them having to reject any pre-existing beliefs that might have implications for their social identity. Fortunately, recent years have seen a growing interest in a method of dialectical conflict resolution that can be seen as an alternative approach to deliberation based on co-creation rather than persuasion (Bartels, 2015; Mansbridge et al., 2010; Nelson, 2017; Stout, 2019; Stout & Love, 2017; Wright, 2019b). This is the idea of integration, developed by the early 20th century American pragmatist philosopher, organizational theorist, and political scientist Mary Parker Follett.
Integration: Conflict Resolution through Co-creation
Follett defines integration as an alternative to the two usual methods of resolving conflict: domination, viz., victory of one side over the other, and compromise, which, in Follett’s view, merely represents a temporary suspension of the conflict that does not resolve the core desires of either side (Follett, 1942). For Follett (1924, p. 208), neither of these approaches can serve as the basis of democratic government and decision making, because they do not reflect the genuine ‘will of the people.’ In integration, by contrast, participants work together to jointly develop a new win–win solution that addresses the underlying desires of each side (Mansbridge et al., 2010). This new solution could not have been formulated by either side in isolation because it reflects the interweaving of individual positions into a new group thought. Integration is achieved by first shifting discussion from the particular issue being debated (which may indeed represent a zero-sum game) to the underlying desires motivating the disagreement, and then searching for a resolution of these desires that is orthogonal to the original axis of conflict.
Follett provides one of her many examples of this process in reference to a disagreement between a man and his live-in mother over the location of the dining room table: the man wanted the table near the window and his mother wanted it in the middle of the room. Although it is undeniable that the table itself cannot be in two places at once, Follett (1924, pp. 169–170) reframes the question, asking the man,
[w]hat did you and your mother really want? Perhaps not-table-in-window or table-in-middle-of-room at all. Perhaps what she really wanted was to have it where it would be near the butler’s pantry, where it would be easier to walk around, or where it would be near the radiator. Perhaps what you really wanted was more light, or the view of the river. The integration might have been to take down the curtains.
Although the prospect for such win–win solutions may seem remote in many contentious political conflicts, Follett (1942) outlines a series of strategies to help identify and facilitate them. These include bringing underlying differences into the open, breaking up larger concepts and problems into smaller ones, and distinguishing between the symbolic and substantive aspects of the conflict, which may be equally important but can often be dealt with separately. Using these methods, it is often possible to identify avenues for integration even between groups whose positions seem diametrically opposed (Wright, 2019a).
Critically, although it predates the development of deliberative democracy, integration can be productively analyzed as an alternative approach to deliberation that replaces the activity of persuasion with that of co-creation. Like deliberation, integration is a form of dialogue aimed at resolving conflicts and making decisions about matters of common concern through non-coercive means. Like deliberative democrats, Follett (1918, p. 180) sees integration as a mechanism for the production of democratic legitimacy that is superior to voting for both intrinsic and instrumental reasons. The primary difference between integration and contemporary accounts of deliberation is, of course, integration’s rejection of persuasion in favor of co-creation. For Follett, persuading my opponents to reject their own beliefs, or to adopt mine, would represent an undemocratic domination, even if it were achieved through the forceless force of argument.9 Because Follett (1942, pp. 30–31) sees conflict as analogous to friction—something that often needs to be managed and controlled but is also a critical source of power for human advancement—she sees the goal of democracy not as eliminating conflict but rather productively channeling conflicts intro creative solutions. Thus, in Follett’s view, a method of conflict resolution that does not make use of the conflict for creative purposes is not genuinely democratic (Follett, 1924, p. 209).
Notwithstanding this key difference, integration has the potential to equal, or in some cases exceed, the instrumental benefits produced by persuasion-based conceptions of deliberation. For example, integration may be better able to harness the ‘error canceling’ power of diversity that serves as the foundation of most epistemic justifications for deliberation (e.g. Bohman, 2006; Estlund, 2008; Hong & Page, 2004; Myers, 2018). This is because, compared to persuasion, co-creation is less vulnerable to groupthink and expert domination (Solomon, 2006) and is explicitly focused on producing a new solution that transcends the perspective and biases of any particular actor (Wright, 2019b).
Because the goal of integration is ‘not to find the best individual thought, but the collective thought’ (Follett, 1918, p. 30), it is not focused on ‘winnowing’ out alternatives and beliefs that cannot be justified by sufficiently strong arguments (Goodin, 2017). Thus, the success of integration is not dependent on participants rejecting beliefs that have implications for their social identity, even when those beliefs cannot be justified. Rather, the goal of integration is for opponents to work together to create a new solution that did not exist before. Because this new idea is aimed at fulfilling the core desires of each side, participants should be able to adopt it without rejecting any of their pre-existing beliefs or unconditionally adopting the position of their opponents. The solution is thus not merely a preexisting belief that participants must be persuaded to accept, regardless of its implications for their social identity. Rather it is, at least partly, their own idea: something that they helped to create and which serves to advance their own interests.
Integration and Persuasion in Deliberations surrounding Vaccination
To illustrate how an approach to deliberation based on integration differs from one based on persuasion in situations of social identity threat, I analyze contemporary debates between vaccine advocates in the mainstream medical community and parents who are part of the vaccine hesitancy or refusal (VHR) movement over whether to vaccinate children against highly contagious and dangerous diseases, such as measles or COVID-19. In reality, the active participation of both groups would be necessary to generate a true deliberative solution to this conflict. However, existing research on the drivers of VHR beliefs can help us predict how these two different approaches to deliberation might produce different results.
In the US at least, VHR beliefs are not generally driven by ignorance about the benefits or risks of vaccines. VHR parents often have high levels of medical or scientific literacy (Gottlieb, 2016) and a high capacity for complex reasoning (Ward et al., 2017). Consequently, efforts to persuade these parents to change their minds by reference to scientific evidence have not been successful (Kata, 2010; Meszaros et al., 1996). Prior to the COVID-19 pandemic VHR beliefs were largely driven by broader distrust of the Western medical establishment and a commitment to a high-intensity mode of parenting that emphasizes continued vigilance and parental control over children’s lives to protect them from harm (Brown et al., 2010; Reich, 2014; Ward et al., 2017). As mentioned above, these beliefs can be strongly connected to parents’ social identity (Attwell & Smith, 2017). Research finds that, for many VHR parents, both their rejection of Western medical knowledge and their commitment to a particular mode of parenting was ‘so totalizing that it came to define their identity and sense of self’ (Ward et al., 2017, p. 7).
This poses a serious challenge for efforts to resolve this dispute via a deliberative approach centered on persuasion. The success of this approach would depend on it being possible to persuade at least some of these parents to revise their opinions about science, medicine, and parenting purely in response to a sufficiently strong opposing argument. But rejecting prior beliefs about vaccine safety, parenting style, and Western medicine would likely produce extreme social identity threat. In effect, it would entail an admission by VHR parents that they have been bad parents and put their own children’s health at risk—one of the very things that motivated their VHR beliefs in the first place.
Furthermore, because many VHR parents also see opposition to the epistemological paradigm of Western medicine in general as an important part of their social identity (Ward et al., 2017), even less ambitious efforts to attain epistemic meta-consensus (Dryzek & Niemeyer, 2006) may produce social identity threat. For VHR parents, even this milder form of consensus—accepting that it is reasonable for proponents of Western medicine to believe in results that have been verified by the methods of natural science—could threaten their social identity.10 We should therefore expect that defensive mechanisms, like motivated reasoning, will protect VHR parents from having to accept these painful conclusions (Sinatra, Kienhues, & Hofer, 2014) even in the face of compelling counter-arguments, thereby preventing deliberation from inducing any substantial change in their beliefs.
Efforts to resolve this dispute via integration and co-creation, by contrast, would recommend shifting the debate from the initial dispute to the underlying desires motivating the positions of each side. For vaccine proponents in the medical establishment, these would presumably include preventing infection by vaccine-targeted diseases and the establishment of herd immunity. For VHR parents, the research above tells us that their core desire is not to avoid vaccinating their child but rather to promote their child’s health; to engage in an active, vigilant style of parenting; and to maintain a skepticism of the Western medical establishment. Indeed, VHR parents often reject the label of ‘anti-vaccine,’ preferring to identify as ‘pro-safe vaccine’ (Kata, 2012). Thus, although the opposing positions in the original dispute (to give a child an existing vaccine or not) are mutually exclusive, this is not necessarily the case for the underlying desires of both sides.
One possible integrative solution might be for vaccine proponents to ask VHR parents for their assistance in developing an alternative, safer (according to VHR parents) version of the vaccine in question that could be offered to members of the public who are skeptical of the mainstream vaccine. There are various ways in which an existing vaccine might be modified to address the concerns of the VHR community without harming its safety and efficacy (as evaluated by vaccine proponents). One example might be the addition of homeopathic compounds. Because members of the VHR community often embrace various forms of alternative medicine, including homeopathy (Kata, 2010), the addition of such compounds might make the vaccine seem safer and better aligned with their own beliefs about health and medicine. Vaccine proponents are unlikely to share these beliefs, but they may be willing to accept the addition of these compounds, because, from the perspective of Western medicine, homeopathic compounds are so diluted that they have no biological effects at all (Grimes, 2012; Hawke, Driel, Buington, McGuire, & King, 2018; Maddox, Randi, & Stewart, 1988) and are thus unlikely to negatively impact the safety or efficacy of the vaccine.
From the perspective of the VHR community, what may be most important is not the substantive content of these changes but the fact that their community had a hand in implementing them. The resulting alternative vaccine, however closely it resembles the previous version from a scientific perspective, may be seen, from the VHR community’s perspective, as fundamentally different insofar as it is a product of the community itself. Critically, VHR parents would still be free to believe that mainstream medical establishment could not have developed a safe vaccine without their assistance, even though this belief likely could not have been justified in the course of a traditional deliberation. Proponents of Western medicine, by contrast, are still free to believe that the contributions of VHR parents to the vaccine (e.g., the addition of homeopathic compounds) had no actual effect on the safety or efficacy of the vaccine, thus preserving their own social identity as practitioners of an epistemically valid scientific paradigm. Yet, despite this continuing disagreement, both groups would achieve the actual outcome that they desired: a vaccine that is perceived as safe and effective by both the medical establishment and VHR parents.
At the same time, it is possible that this integrative process might still lead participants to eventually revise their existing beliefs. For example, the experience of working together with members of the medical establishment to solve a problem may cause some members of the VHR community to gradually reevaluate their distrust of Western medicine, perhaps even to the point where acceptance of even mainstream vaccines no longer poses a threat. This is, in fact, the mechanism by which Follett sees integration eventually leading to the revision of existing beliefs, in situations where persuasion itself is infeasible:
[t]he theory of consent rests on the assumptions that we think with our “minds” and we don’t…. How often we see cases where we have not been able to persuade people, by our most careful reasoning, to think differently, but later, by giving them an opportunity to enter on a certain course of action, their “minds” are thereby changed (Follett, 1924, p. 198).
Thus, although the rejection of existing beliefs is not a requirement of integration, it may be a byproduct.
In reality, of course, this proposed solution may be unsatisfactory to one or both sides of this conflict. Integrative solutions often seem radical and unsatisfactory, because, by their nature, they incorporate what we see as unjustified ideas from the opposing side. Follett (1942, p. 36), herself, cautions that integrative solutions are not always possible, and they may not even be desirable in all situations. However, expanding our understanding of deliberation to include integration as a possible mechanism for belief change alongside persuasion may increase the likelihood of successful deliberation in situations where social identity threat and motivated reasoning insulates participants from the forceless force of argument.
Conclusion
Some of the most contentious conflicts facing democratic societies around the world are deeply connected to social identity, which may explain why they have proven so intractable. The viability of deliberation as a basis of democratic legitimacy depends on its ability to resolve these sorts of conflicts, but this may not be possible through an approach based solely on reason-giving and persuasion. For these conflicts, an integrative approach that rejects persuasion in favor of co-creation may offer the most viable strategy for deliberative transformation. More empirical research is needed on the effectiveness of integration in practice, but the power of social identity threat recommends that this research may be of critical importance to the project of deliberative democracy.
Notes
- Of course, determining whether deliberation has actually changed minds is hardly trivial. Curato, Dryzek, Ercan, Hendriks, and Niemeyer (2017, p. 32) note that while ‘[d]eliberation by definition requires amenability to preference transformation’ true ‘deliberative transformation’ may operate over longer time periods than those common in many contemporary research designs. ⮭
- See also Gutmann and Thomson (2004, p. 41), Rosenberg (2014, p. 101), Steenbergen, Bächtiger, Spörndli, and Steiner (2003, p. 25). ⮭
- See also Chambers (2009, p. 341). ⮭
- For example, Dryzek and List (2003) discuss four possible mechanisms by which deliberation might induce belief change, three of which (informational, argumentative, and reflective) can be seen as subcategories of persuasion, insofar as they all involve the justification of existing opinions or preferences by information or arguments. The fourth ‘social’ mechanism involves the act of deliberation helping participants to better recognize their interrelationship with a social group (Dryzek & List 2003, p. 9). This does seem to go beyond persuasion, but the extent to which deliberation’s social aspect could, by itself, produce successful deliberative outcomes in situations where persuasion is ineffective is not discussed in detail. ⮭
- Goodin (2017) does see the ‘generation’ of new alternatives as an important initial stage in deliberation, followed by a ‘winnowing’ down of those alternatives through critique. However, even in this formulation the generation stage of deliberation is framed as a brainstorming session where participants are encouraged to lay out all of their own (pre-existing) ideas. Although it is clearly possible that the brainstorming session could lead to the creation of a genuinely new idea that none of the participants had previously held, this possibility is never discussed. Similarly, other discussions of the creative power of deliberation often imply that this creativity is limited to the production of new reasons or justifications for existing ideas, rather than genuinely new opinions or ideas. For example, Owen and Smith (2015, p. 219) argue that deliberation is a ‘creative process in which novel shared reasons can emerge within the activity of reasoning together as equals’ (emphasis added). ⮭
- ‘What counts as a “good reason” manifests itself only in the role it has in an argumentation game’ (Habermas, 1996, p. 227). ⮭
- Similar findings highlighting cognitive biases as mechanisms for managing information that threatens social identity can be found in literature on cognitive dissonance (Cooper, 2007; Festinger, 1965; Festinger, Riecken, & Schachter, 1965). ⮭
- See e.g., Bächtiger et al. (2010, p. 49), ‘actors must have a certain willingness to find a rational consensus in order to make productive and creative deliberation happen,’ and Neblo et al. (2018, p. 130), ‘even if citizens learn factual information via participation, are they willing to engage each other and their representatives in a constructive, reason-giving conversation?’ Dryzek (2005, p. 219) likewise warns that the deliberative requirement of ‘openness to persuasion by critical argument’ is ‘explicitly rejected by (say) fundamentalist Christians.’ ⮭
- Anticipating the criticism of Mouffe (1999), Young (1996), and other agonists and difference democrats, Follett (1924, p. 200) argues that ‘[i]n many of the methods used to “persuade,” consent becomes hardly distinguishable from coercion.’ ⮭
- The same challenge would likely face scientists and doctors within the medical establishment for whom the epistemic authority of positivist methods (e.g., randomized control trials, peer review, replication of results, and statistical significance tests) is a key part of their own social identity as practitioners of science. For these individuals, even agreeing that it is reasonable for VHR parents to reject the overwhelming scientific evidence on the safety and efficacy of vaccines might similarly induce a form of social identity threat. ⮭
Competing Interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
1 Abramowitz, A. I., & McCoy, J. (2019). United States: Racial Resentment, Negative Partisanship, and Polarization in Trump’s America. The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 681(1), 137–156. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0002716218811309
2 Attwell, K., & Smith, D. T. (2017). Parenting as politics: social identity theory and vaccine hesitant communities. International Journal of Health Governance, 22(3), 183–198. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1108/IJHG-03-2017-0008
3 Bächtiger, A., Dryzek, J. S., Mansbridge, J., & Warren, M. E. (2018). Deliberative Democracy: An Introduction In A. Bächtiger, J. S. Dryzek, J. Mansbridge, & M. E. Warren (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198747369.001.0001
4 Bächtiger, A., Niemeyer, S., Neblo, M., Steenbergen, M. R., & Steiner, J. (2010). Symposium: Toward More Realistic Models of Deliberative Democracy Disentangling Diversity in Deliberative Democracy: Competing Theories, Their Blind Spots and Complementarities. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(1), 32–63. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00342.x
5 Barabas, J. (2004). How Deliberation Affects Policy Opinions. American Political Science Review, 98(4), 687–701. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055404041425
6 Bartels, K. P. R. (2015). Communicative Capacity: Public encounters in participatory theory and practice. Bristol, UK: Policy Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt1t89b54
7 Batalha, L. M., Niemeyer, S., Dryzek, J. S., & Gastil, J. (2019). Psychological Mechanisms of Deliberative Transformation: The Role of Group Identity. Journal of Public Deliberation, 15(1), 1–20. DOI: http://doi.org/10.16997/jdd.313
8 Bohman, J. (2006). Deliberative Democracy and the Epistemic Benefits of Diversity. Episteme, 3(3), 175–190. DOI: http://doi.org/10.3366/epi.2006.3.3.175
9 Branscombe, N. R., Ellemers, N., Spears, R., & Dooje, B. (1999). The context and content of social identity threat. In N. Ellemers, R. Spears, & B. Dooje (Eds.), Social Identity: Context, Commitment, Content (pp. 35–58). Oxford, UK: Blackwell Science.
10 Breakwell, G. M. (2015). Coping with Threatened Identities. DOI: http://doi.org/10.4324/9781315733913
11 Brown, K. F., Kroll, J. S., Hudson, M. J., Ramsay, M., Green, J., Long, S. J., … Sevdalis, N. (2010). Factors underlying parental decisions about combination childhood vaccinations including MMR: A systematic review. Vaccine, 28(26), 4235–4248. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.vaccine.2010.04.052
12 Chambers, S. (2009). Rhetoric and the Public Sphere: has Deliberative Democracy Abandoned Mass Democracy? Political Theory, 37(3), 323–350. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0090591709332336
13 Chung, H., & Duggan, J. (2020). A Formal Theory of Democratic Deliberation. American Political Science Review, 114(1), 14–35. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055419000674
14 Cohen, G. L., Aronson, J., & Steele, C. M. (2000). When Beliefs Yield to Evidence: Reducing Biased Evaluation by Affirming the Self. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 26(9), 1151–1164. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/01461672002611011
15 Cohen, G. L., Sherman, D. K., Bastardi, A., Hsu, L., McGoey, M., & Ross, L. (2007). Bridging the Partisan Divide: Self-Affirmation Reduces Ideological Closed-Mindedness and Inflexibility in Negotiation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(3), 415–430. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.93.3.415
16 Cooper, J. (2007). Cognitive Dissonance: Fifty Years of a Classic Theory. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications Inc.
17 Cruwys, T., Stevens, M., & Greenawa, K. H. (2020). A social identity perspective on COVID-19: Health risk is affected by shared group membership. Brritish Journal of Social Psychology, 59(3), 584–593. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/bjso.12391
18 Curato, N., Dryzek, J. S., Ercan, S. A., Hendriks, C. M., & Niemeyer, S. (2017). Twelve Key Findings in Deliberative Democracy Research. Deadalus, 146(3), 28–38. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/DAED_a_00444
19 Dalton, A. N., & Huang, L. (2013). Motivated Forgetting in Response to Social Identity Threat. Journal of Consumer Research, 40(6), 1017–1038. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1086/674198
20 Dryzek, J. S. (2000). Deliberative Democracy and Beyond. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
21 Dryzek, J. S. (2005). Deliberative Democracy in Divided Societies: Alternatives to Agonism and Analgesia. Political Theory, 33(2), 218–242. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0090591704268372
22 Dryzek, J. S. (2017). The Forum, the System, and the Polity: Three Varieties of Democratic Theory. Political Theory, 45(5), 610–636. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0090591716659114
23 Dryzek, J. S., Bächtiger, A., Chambers, S., Cohen, J., Druckman, J. N., Felicetti, A., … Warren, M. E. (2019). The crisis of democracy and the science of deliberation. Science, 363(6432), 1144–1146. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaw2694
24 Dryzek, J. S., & List, C. (2003). Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation. British Journal of Political Science, 33(1), 1–28. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123403000012
25 Dryzek, J. S., & Niemeyer, S. (2006). Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals. American Journal of Political Science, 50(3), 634–649. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2006.00206.x
26 Estlund, D. M. (2008). Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9781400831548
27 Festinger, L. (1965). A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
28 Festinger, L., Riecken, H. W., & Schachter, S. (1965). When Prophecy Fails. New York, NY: Harper Torchbooks.
29 Fishkin, J. S., & Luskin, R. C. (2005). Experimenting with a Democratic Ideal: Deliberative Polling and Public Opinion. Acta Politica, 40(1), 284–298. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.ap.5500121
30 Follett, M. P. (1918). The New State: Group Organization the Solution of Popular Government. London, UK: Longmans, Green and Co.
31 Follett, M. P. (1924). Creative Experience. New York, NY: Longmans, Green and Co.
32 Follett, M. P. (1942). Constructive Conflict. In H. C. Metcalf & L. Urwick (Eds.), Dynamic Administration: The Collected Papers of Mary Parker Follett. New York: Harper and Brothers Publishers.
33 Goodin, R. E. (2000). Democratic Deliberation Within. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 29(1), 81–109. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2000.00081.x
34 Goodin, R. E. (2008). Innovating Democracy: Democratic Theory and Practice After the Deliberative Turn. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199547944.001.0001
35 Goodin, R. E. (2017). The epistemic benefits of deliberative democracy. Policy Sciences, 50(3), 351–366. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11077-017-9286-0
36 Gottlieb, S. D. (2016). Vaccine resistances reconsidered: Vaccine skeptics and the Jenny McCarthy effect. BioSocieties, 11(1), 152–174. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1057/biosoc.2015.30
37 Green, D., Palmquist, B., & Schickler, E. (2002). Partisan Hearts and Minds: Political Parties and the Social Identities of Voters. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
38 Grimes, D. R. (2012). Proposed mechanisms for homeopathy are physically impossible. Focus on Alternative and Compelmentary Therapies, 17(3), 149–155. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.2042-7166.2012.01162.x
39 Gutmann, A., & Thomson, D. (2004). Why Deliberative Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9781400826339
40 Habermas, J. (1996). Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
41 Habermas, J. (2006). Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still Enjoy an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empirical Research. Communications Theory, 16(4), 411–426. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2885.2006.00280.x
42 Hawke, K., Driel, M. L. v., Buington, B. J., McGuire, T. M., & King, D. (2018). Homeopathic medicinal products for preventing and treating acute respiratory tract infections in children. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews, 2018(p), 1–62. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1002/14651858.CD005974.pub5
43 Hong, L., & Page, S. E. (2004). Groups of diverse problem solvers can outperform groups of high-ability problem solvers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 101(46), 16385–16389. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0403723101
44 Hoog, N. D. (2012). Processing of Social Identity Threats: A Defense Motivation Perspective. Social Psychology, 44(6), 361–372. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1027/1864-9335/a000133
45 Iyengar, S., Lelkes, Y., Levendusky, M., Malhotra, N., & Westwood, S. J. (2019). The Origins and Consequences of Affective Polarization in the United States. Annual Review of Political Science, 22(7), 129–146. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-polisci-051117-073034
46 Kahan, D. M. (2015). The Politically Motivated Reasoning Paradigm, Part 1: What Politically Motivated Reasoning Is and How to Measure It. In R. A. Scott, S. M. Kosslyn, & M. C. Buchmann (Eds.), Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1002/9781118900772.etrds0417
47 Kata, A. (2010). A postmodern Pandora’s box: Anti-vaccination misinformation on the Internet. Vaccine, 28(7), 1709–1716. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.vaccine.2009.12.022
48 Kata, A. (2012). Anti-vaccine activists, Web 2.0, and the postmodern paradigm – An overview of tactics and tropes used online by the anti-vaccination movement. Vaccine, 30(25), 3778–3789. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.vaccine.2011.11.112
49 Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Second ed.). Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
50 Kukucka, J., Kassin, S. M., Zapf, P. A., & Drorc, I. E. (2017). Cognitive Bias and Blindness: A Global Survey of Forensic Science Examiners. Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition, 6(4), 452–459. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jarmac.2017.09.001
51 Kunda, Z. (1990). The Case for Motivated Reasoning. Pyschological Bulletin, 108(3), 480–498. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.108.3.480
52 Lafont, C. (2020). Democracy without Shortcuts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198848189.001.0001
53 List, C. (2018). Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice: A Review. In A. Bächtiger, J. S. Dryzek, J. Mansbridge, & M. E. Warren (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy (pp. 463–489). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198747369.013.14
54 Mackie, G. (2006). Does democratic deliberation change minds? Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 5(3), 279–303. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X06068301
55 Maddox, J., Randi, J., & Stewart, W. W. (1988). “High-dilution” experiments a delusion. Nature, 334, 287–334. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1038/334287a0
56 Mansbridge, J., Bohman, J., Chambers, S., Christiano, T., Fung, A., Parkinson, J., … Warren, M. E. (2012). A systemic approach to deliberative democracy. In J. Parkinson & J. Mansbridge (Eds.), Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
57 Mansbridge, J., Bohman, J., Chambers, S., Estlund, D., Føllesdal, A., Fung, A., … Martí, J. l. (2010). The Place of Self-Interest and the Role of Power in Deliberative Democracy. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(1), 64–100. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00344.x
58 Már, K., & Gastil, J. (2020). Tracing the Boundaries of Motivated Reasoning: How Deliberative Minipublics Can Improve Voter Knowledge. Political Psychology, 41(1), 107–127. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/pops.12591
59 Mason, L. (2018). Ideolouges Without Issues: The Polarizing Consequences of Ideological Identities. Public Opinion Quarterly, 82, 280–301. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/poq/nfy005
60 Meszaros, J. R., Asch, D., Baron, J., Hershey, J. C., Kunreuther, H., & Schwartz-Buzaglo, J. (1996). Cognitive Processes and the Decisions of Some Parents to Forego Pertussis Vaccination for Their Children. Journal of Clinical Epidemology, 49(6), 697–703. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/0895-4356(96)00007-8
61 Mouffe, C. (1999). Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism? Social Research, 66(3), 745–758.
62 Myers, C. D. (2018). Political Deliberation, Interest Conflict, and the Common Knowledge Effect. Journal of Public Deliberation, 14(1). DOI: http://doi.org/10.16997/jdd.296
63 Nauroth, P., Gollwitzer, M., Bender, J., & Rothmund, T. (2014). Social Identity Threat Motivates Science-Discrediting Online Comments. PLOS ONE, 1–26. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0117476
64 Nauroth, P., Gollwitzer, M., Kozuchowski, H., Bender, J., & Rothmund, T. (2017). The effects of social identity threat and social identity affirmation on laypersons’ perception of scientists. Public Understanding of Science, 26(7), 254–770. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0963662516631289
65 Neblo, M. A., Esterling, K. M., & Lazer, D. M. J. (2018). Politics with the People: Building a Directly Representative Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/9781316338179
66 Nelson, G. M. (2017). Mary Parker Follett – Creativity and Democracy. Human Service Organizations: Management, Leadership & Governance, 41(2), 178–185. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1080/23303131.2016.1263073
67 Owen, D., & Smith, G. (2015). Survey Article: Deliberation, Democracy, and the Systemic Turn. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 23(2), 213–234. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12054
68 Pronin, E., Gilovich, T., & Ross, L. (2004). Objectivity in the Eye of the Beholder: Divergent Perceptions of Bias in Self Versus Others. Psychological Review, 111(3), 781–799. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.111.3.781
69 Pronin, E., Lin, D. Y., & Ross, L. (2002). The Bias Blind Spot: Perceptions of Bias in Self Versus Others. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28(3), 369–381. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0146167202286008
70 Redlawsk, D. P., Civettini, A. J. W., & Emmerson, K. M. (2010). The Affective Tipping Point: Do Motivated Reasoners Ever “Get It”? Political Psychology, 31(4), 563–593. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9221.2010.00772.x
71 Reich, J. A. (2014). Neoliberal Mothering and Vaccine Refusal: Imagined Gated Communities and the Privlege of Choice. Gender and Society, 28(5), 697–704. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0891243214532711
72 Richey, M. (2012). Motivated Reasoning in Political Information Processing: The Death Knell of Deliberative Democracy? Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 42(4), 511–542. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0048393111430761
73 Rosenberg, S. W. (2014). Citizen competence and the psychology of deliberation. In S. Elstub & P. McLaverty (Eds.), Deliberative Democracy: Issues and Cases. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9780748643509-008
74 Schulz, A., Wirth, W., & Müller, P. (2020). We Are the People and You Are Fake News: A Social Identity Approach to Populist Citizens’ False Consensus and Hostile Media Perceptions. Communication Research, 47(2), 201–226. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0093650218794854
75 Sinatra, G. M., Kienhues, D., & Hofer, B. K. (2014). Addressing Challenges to Public Understanding of Science: Epistemic Cognition, Motivated Reasoning, and Conceptual Change. Educational Psychologist, 49(2), 123–138. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1080/00461520.2014.916216
76 Slothuus, R., & Vreese, C. H. d. (2010). Political Parties, Motivated Reasoning, and Issue Framing Effects. The Journal of Politics, 72(3), 630–645. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S002238161000006X
77 Solomon, M. (2006). Groupthink versus The Wisdom of Crowds: The Social Epistemology of Deliberation and Dissent The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44(S1), 28–42. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2006.tb00028.x
78 Steenbergen, M. R., Bächtiger, A., Spörndli, M., & Steiner, J. (2003). Measuring Political Deliberation: A Discourse Quality Index. Comparative European Politics, 1(1), 21–48. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.cep.6110002
79 Sternisko, A., Cichocka, A., & Bave, J. J. V. (2020). The dark side of social movements: social identity, non-conformity, and the lure of conspiracy theories. Current Opinion in Psychology, 35(1), 1–6. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc.2020.02.007
80 Stout, M. (Ed.) (2019). The Future of Progressivism: Applying Follettian Thinking to Contemporary Issues. Claremont, CA: Process Century Press.
81 Stout, M., & Love, J. M. (2017). Integrative Governance: A Method for Fruitful Public Encounters. American Review of Public Administration, 47(1), 130–147. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/0275074015576953
82 Strickler, R. (2018). Deliberate with the Enemy? Polarization, Social Identity, and Attitudes toward Disagreement. Political Research Quarterly, 71(1), 3–18. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1177/1065912917721371
83 Taber, C. S., & Lodge, M. (2006). Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs. American Journal of Political Science, 50(3), 755–769. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2006.00214.x
84 Taber, C. S., & Lodge, M. (2016). The Illusion of Choice in Democratic Politics: The Unconscious Impact of Motivated Political Reasoning. Political Psychology, 37(S1), 61–85. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/pops.12321
85 Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1979). An Integrative Theory of Intergroup Conflict. In W. G. Austin & S. Worchel (Eds.), The Social Psychology of Integroup Relations (pp. 33–47). Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole.
86 Ward, P. R., Attwell, K., Meyer, S. B., Rokkas, P., & Leask, J. (2017). Understanding the perceived logic of care by vaccine-hesitant and vaccine-refusing parents: A qualitative study in Australia. PLOS ONE, 12(10), 1–15. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0185955
87 West, E. A., & Iyengar, S. (2020). Partisanship as a Social Identity: Implications for Polarization. Political Behavior. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11109-020-09637-y
88 Wright, G. (2019a). From Domination to Integration: Dealing with Polarized Views of Race in Contemporary American Politics. In M. Stout (Ed.), The Future of Progressivism: Applying Follettian Thinking to Contemporary Issues. Claremont, CA: Process Century Press.
89 Wright, G. (2019b). Integrative Democracy: Mary Parker Follett’s Integration and Deliberative Democracy. Journal of Public Deliberation, 15(1), 1–25. DOI: http://doi.org/10.16997/jdd.315
90 Young, I. M. (1996). Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy. In S. Benhabib (Ed.), Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9780691234168-007
91 Zhang, K. (2019). Encountering Dissimilar Views in Deliberation: Political Knowledge, Attitude Strength, and Opinion Change. Political Psychology, 40(2), 315–333. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/pops.12514